Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T12:56:19.064Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Is Humanitarian Intervention Legal? The Rule of Law in an Incoherent World

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 September 2011

Abstract

The paper asks whether humanitarian intervention is legal and reviews contemporary legal arguments on both sides. It finds that both views are sustainable by conventional accounts of the sources of international law; humanitarian intervention is at once legal and illegal. The paper then considers the implications of this for the idea of the rule of law in world politics. The power of international law in this case comes from its utility as a resource for justifying state policies, not as a means for distinguishing compliance from non-compliance. Law remains important to world politics, but in a different way than usually understood.

Type
Features
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

NOTES

1 For these debates, see, e.g., Diplomatic Academy of Vienna, The UN Security Council and the Responsibility to Protect: Policy, Process, and Practice (Vienna: Favorita Papers 01/2010); Wheeler, Nicholas J., Saving Strangers: Humanitarian Intervention in International Society (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003)Google Scholar; and Holzgrefe, J. L. and Keohane, Robert O., eds., Humanitarian Intervention: Ethical, Legal, and Political Dilemmas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 See Johnson, James Turner, Ideology, Reason, and the Limitation of War (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975)Google Scholar; Clark, Ian, Legitimacy in International Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005)Google Scholar; and Gray, Christine D., International Law and the Use of Force, 3rd. ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)Google Scholar.

3 See, e.g., Jolly, Richard, Emmerij, Louis, and Weiss, Thomas G., UN Ideas That Changed the World (Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press, 2009)Google Scholar.

4 Controversy over whether the Council is correctly identifying such threats is common—for instance, with respect to the Libyan sanctions in the 1990s. See Martenczuk, B., “The Security Council, the International Court and Judicial Review: What Lessons from Lockerbie?European Journal of International Law 10, no. 3 (1999), pp. 517–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Gray, International Law and the Use of Force.

6 “Productive” here is used in the sense used by Barnett, Michael N. and Duvall, Raymond, eds., Power in Global Governance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005)Google Scholar.

7 United Nations Security Council Resolution 487.

8 These words first appear in a letter from Daniel Webster to Lord Ashburton, August 6, 1842; avalon.law.yale.edu/19th_century/br-1842d.asp#web2; accessed November 18, 2010.

9 Byers, Michael, “Jumping the Gun,” London Review of Books 24, no. 11 (2002), pp. 35Google Scholar.

10 See International Court of Justice, Nicaragua Merits, ICJ Reports, June 27, 1986, 94, para. 176.

11 See, generally, Lowe, Vaughan and Tzanakopoulos, Antonios, “Humanitarian Intervention,” in Wolfrum, Rüdiger, ed., Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010)Google Scholar; Alston, Philip and MacDonald, Euan, eds., Human Rights, Intervention, and the Use of Force (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Finnemore, Martha, The Purpose of Intervention: Changing Beliefs about the Use of Force (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2004)Google Scholar; and Franck, Thomas M., Recourse to Force: State Action Against Threats and Armed Attacks (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Sturchler, Nikolas, The Threat of Force in International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006)Google Scholar.

13 Hurd, Ian, After Anarchy: Legitimacy and Power in the UN Security Council (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007)Google Scholar.

14 Brownlie, Ian, “‘International Law and the Use of Force by States’ Revisited,” Chinese Journal of International Law 1, no. 1 (2002), pp. 119CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 Swedish representative at the UN Security Council, cited in Gray, International Law and the Use of Force, pp. 32–33.

16 Simma, Bruno et al. , eds., The Charter of the United Nations: A Commentary (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002)Google Scholar.

17 Corfu Channel, International Court of Justice, 1949.

18 Russell, Ruth B., A History of the UN Charter: The Role of the United States (Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution, 1958)Google Scholar; and Lowe and Tzanakopoulos, “Humanitarian Intervention.”

19 Inter-American Democratic Charter, September 11, 2001, Lima, Peru; www.oas.org/charter/docs/resolution1_en_p4.htm.

20 Fassbender, Bardo, “Rediscovering a Forgotten Constitution: Notes on the Place of the UN Charter in the International Legal Order,” in Dunoff, Jeffrey L. and Trachtman, Joel P., eds., Ruling the World? Constitutionalism, International Law, and Global Governance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009)Google Scholar; Boon, Kristen E., “Regime Conflicts and the UN Security Council: Applying the Law of Responsibility,” George Washington International Law Review 42, no. 2 (2010)Google Scholar; and Richard Burchill, “Regional Arrangements as an Expression of Diversity in the International System” (paper presented at the American Society of International Law workshop on international organizations, October 29, 2010, Washington, D.C.).

21 Byers, “Jumping the Gun.”

22 Independent International Commission on Kosovo, Kosovo Report: Conflict, International Response, Lessons Learned (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000)Google Scholar.

23 Brownlie, “International Law,” p. 16; and Franck, Recourse to Force. See also Simma, Bruno, “NATO, the UN, and the Use of Force: Legal Aspects,” European Journal of International Law 10, no. 1 (1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Roberts, Anthea, “Legality vs. Legitimacy: Can Uses of Force Be Illegal but Justified?” in Alston, Philip and MacDonald, Euan, eds., Human Rights, Intervention, and the Use of Force (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008)Google Scholar.

24 Franck, Thomas M., “Who Killed Article 2(4)? Or: Changing Norms Governing the Use of Force by States,” American Journal of International Law 64 (1970), pp. 810CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 809.

25 Ibid., p. 835.

26 Glennon, Michael, “The Fog of Law: Self-Defense, Inherence, and Incoherence in Article 51 of the United Nations Charter,” Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 25 (2002), pp. 539–58Google Scholar, at 539. See also Glennon, Michael, “How International Rules Die,” Georgetown Law Journal 93 (2005), p. 939Google Scholar.

27 Glennon, “The Fog of Law,” p. 540, emphasis added.

28 In the United States, see Poe v. Ullman at the U.S. Supreme Court (1961), and Committee on Legal Ethics v. Prinz in the West Virginia Supreme Court, 1992.

29 The argument may be logically sound, but it is empirically weak since it ignores a vast universe of state practice that contradicts it. Most state behavior upholds and reinforces the ban on war, and all of this is evidence against the argument of desuetude.

30 Smith, Michael J., “Humanitarian Intervention: An Overview of the Ethical Issues,” Ethics & International Affairs 12 (1998), pp. 6379CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 66.

31 Weiss, Thomas G. and Thakur, Ramesh, Global Governance and the UN: An Unfinished Journey (Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press, 2010)Google Scholar; see also the essays in Diplomatic Academy of Vienna, The UN Security Council and the Responsibility to Protect.

32 Kofi Annan, cited in Weiss and Thakur, Global Governance and the UN, p. 318.

33 “2005 World Summit Outcome: Fact Sheet”; www.un.org/summit2005/presskit/fact_sheet.pdf; accessed January 10, 2011.

34 Bellamy, Alex J., “The Responsibility to Protect—Five Years On,” Ethics & International Affairs 24, no. 2 (Summer 2010), pp. 143–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

35 As defined by Adler, Emanuel and Pouliot, Vincent, The Practice Turn in International Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011)Google Scholar.

36 Williams, Paul D. and Bellamy, Alex J., “The Responsibility to Protect and the Crisis in Darfur,” Security Dialogue 36, no. 1 (2005), pp. 2747CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 Reported in Kirkpatrick, David D. and Fahim, Kareen, “Libya Blames Islamic Militants and the West for Unrest,” New York Times, February 28, 2011Google Scholar.

38 Buchanan, Allen, Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007)Google Scholar.

39 Tesón, Fernando R., “The Liberal Case for Humanitarian Intervention,” in Holzgrefe, J. L. and Keohane, Robert O., eds., Humanitarian Intervention: Ethical, Legal, and Political Dilemmas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), p. 93CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

40 UN General Assembly, “An Agenda for Peace,” Report of the Secretary-General, A/47/277, June 17, 1992.

41 Evans, Gareth and Sahnoun, Mohamed, “The Responsibility to Protect,” Foreign Affairs 81, no. 6 (2002), pp. 99110CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 102.

42 Tamanaha, Brian, Law as a Means to an End: Threat to the Rule of Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43 Ibid., pp. 1–2.

44 Koh, Harold Hongju, “Why Do Nations Obey International Law?Yale Law Journal 106, no. 8 (1997), pp. 25992659CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hathaway, Oona, “Do Human Rights Treaties Make a Difference,” Yale Law Journal 111, no. 3 (2002), pp. 19352042CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kelley, Judith, “Who Keeps International Commitments and Why? The International Criminal Court and Bilateral Non-Surrender Agreements,” American Political Science Review 101, no. 3 (2007), pp. 573–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Emilie Hafner-Burton, Jon Pevehouse, and Jana von Stein, “Human Rights Institutions, Membership, and Compliance” (paper presented at the American Political Science Association annual meetings 2009).

45 Kelley, “Who Keeps International Commitments and Why?”

46 Howse, Robert and Teitel, Ruti, “Beyond Compliance: Rethinking Why International Law Matters,” Global Policy 1, no. 2 (2010), pp. 127–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 Exceptions exist, including the interesting case of the “waiver of illegality” position discussed above. This position, common on Kosovo, reveals an underlying prioritization among laws, obligations, and interests that is unconventional: proponents are suggesting that states should obey their international obligations only as long as these obligations are consistent with deeply held norms and interests and when they conflict, compliance is not required (or expected, or desired).

48 See the discussion in Brunnée, Jutta and Toope, Stephen J., Legitimacy and Legality in International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.